The positivist line in the history of the sciences can always
be distinguished by one general assumption, which is that the present state of
the sciences represents some kind of natural division of labor. In other words,
the sciences as now constituted really do cut at the joints, so that we have
clearcut, naturally founded divisions that are entailed by the subjects that
the sciences study: astronomy is the result of studying the stars, economics is
the result of studying exchange, psychology is the result of studying the mind,
etc. Given this viewpoint, there is a certain teleology that organizes the whole
narrative: astrology is the predecessor of astronomy, alchemy the predecessor of
chemistry, etc.
Against this idea, the non-positivist looks at the sciences
as defined by their social environment. Instead of looking at astrology as the
study of the stars, it looks at astrology as a compound of the study of the
stars, the study of the temperaments, and the study of governance. Instead of
looking at alchemy as the study of the rocks or the molecules, it sees alchemy
as operating as the study of treasure, the study of cryptography, the study of
natural symbolism, etc. In other words, there is less joint here, and more
tentacle.
The consequence of the non-positivist line is that we work
outward from what the discipline said about itself at time x, and what was assumed
about it at time x, instead of working inward from an exterior view about what
we know, now, at time y, about the supposed contents of the science. The advantage
of the first view is that we can catch in our net many, many connections that
have been pruned away as the dominant episteme changed. And we become more aware
that the conceptual oppositions that are assumed in positivism are products of
a teleology rather than of an immersive reading of the sources.
Take, for instance, materialism.
It is often assumed that a great leap forward in the
sciences occurred in the 17th and 18th century as a
materialist program was organized to delimit and define acceptable explanations
of natural phenomena. In opposition, there was a supernatural program that
looked around to transcend the mere causal schema.
In fact, this view of the materialist program is very much a
product of late nineteenth century positivism. The oppositions, in the
eighteenth century, was much mushier than this. One of the problems that thinkers
– the zemstvo, the intellectuals in the field, the doctors, lawyers, notaries,
teachers, as well as writers – faced was that they grew up in a world of
certain beliefs that seemed not to be absolutely unfounded. Their grandparents
believed that certain people could, through sacrifice to the devil, transform
themselves into beasts – and their parents definitely believed that certain people
had the gift of finding water or treasure using a kind of cleft stick. They
knew their parents, and some of them knew their grandparents, and they weren’t
insane. They weren’t even stupid. So what was going on?
Materialism, far from opposing these beliefs, helped to
explain them. Of course, certain superstitions were rejected – the belief in werewolves
for instance or vampires required a very complex explanation, and usually the
thought was: this is the delusion of ignorant peasants. But certain
superstitions, properly understood, revealed a primitive grasp of material connections.
Just as the sun’s gravity – that invisible force – explained the rotation of
planets around it, so, too, astrology, properly considered, was all about
cosmic forces that were material things, and could be discovered empirically.
Or, to put a point on this: the demystification of
superstition did not lead to the rejection of those things we might think of as
“superstition”, but rather their re-enactment in other terms.
No comments:
Post a Comment