If you are a man or woman of a certain age,
according to all the wisdom literature I know, and it is a peaceful Sunday
morning, and the adventures that have been the wind in your back - or the life
you have sloughed - have come to a standstill for one moment, then you turn
your reflections to time and its possibility, or even its possible
non-existence, a non-existence that would annul the fact that you are a man or
woman of a certain age, that it is Sunday, that adventure could have ever
happened to you, and that you have a moment to reflect.
Reflect on time one must, because we are not
watches. Watches toil not, neither do they sow – even though our language has
given them hands and a face. Instead, they infinitely visit the same
neighborhood of numbers. One can imagine watches different –one can imagine a
little computer that you could strap to your wrist and that would just record
the seconds, like a timepiece on a bomb, and thus give you a finegrained sense
of your slice and dice advance towards death – or why stop there? Buried with
such a thing, it could go on slicing and dicing your decay, your dust, the
process of your vacuuming up from this world. But at no point in its slicing
and dicing would there be a moment, an aberrant moment, in which it wondered if
it was really going anywhere, or measuring anything.
My two favorite essays on time are McTaggart’s The Unreality of Time and Borges’ A New Refutation of Time. Borges, in the
introduction to his essay, acknowledges the awkwardness of refuting time one
more time again – and concedes that it may be that the evident solecism of the
title may represent the hidden solecism that skews every sentence, so drenched
is language in time, or at least, so much do our assumptions about time live in
our language. It is through looking up the literature on Borges that I first
heard about McTaggart. Borges’ essay is all low violin sounds, all elegy and
fugue – McTaggart’s, on the other hand, is that curious thing, English
idealism, all Gilbert and Sullivan, in which the brisk dispatch of a
philosophical problem seems in stylistic contradiction with its import.
Indeed, it is a question that is little asked why
idealism took so long to take any root in Europe, and why, when it did, it
chose the most material of cultures to do so, Britain. One expects the true
idealist to be scrawny, nearly naked, and with a beggar’s bowl before him – not
peruked, buttoned up, and with snuff and ale within easy reach. But I would
guess that the introduction of idealism in Europe through Britain has something
to do with the British tradition of the ludicrous. English literature loves the
ludicrous – it loves the Liliputians for their own sake. It loves a certain
kind of children’s literature, it loves limericks, it loves to add that one extra
and unnecessary feature that is not at all the effect of the real, but the
effect of the unreal in the real – hence, Dicken’s penchant for describing the
tics of his characters. If we think of idealism as the quintessence of the
ludicrous, then I think we get close to why idealism first found a serious place
in Britain – and why it is so different there than in, say, the philosophical
systems of India, even if there exists some similarity of arguments.
John Ellis McTaggart came, of course, at the end of
the great British idealist tradition. And he was overshadowed by Russell and
Whitehead. In Arthur Quinn’s The Confidence of British Philosophers, there is a
story that I would like to juxtapose to my ludicrous theory. When McTaggart
died, he had only one disciple left, it seems: C.D. Broad. Broad edited the
second edition fo McTaggart’s The Nature of Existence (1928), which fell still
born from the press – and unlike Hume’s Treatise, which had a similar fate,
never experienced any resuscitation by the next generation of philosophers.
Broad was disgusted by the reception of his master’s masterpiece, and wrote a
three volume exposition of the work, which ran to 1200 pages. And in this
exhaustive work, according to Quinn, Broad praised McTaggart’s arguments for
their clarity, and showed that “McTaggart’s most important proofs were
virtually all fallacious...” From the deeper idealistic level, Broad could not
have done McTaggart a greater favor. Truth is one of the superstitions one must
remove from one’s mind in order to truly de-provincialize it – for after all,
holding onto the truth is only a means of separating oneself from God, or
Nothingness.
With this caution, I’ll move on to McTaggart’s
paper.
McTaggart begins with a premise that subsequently
became famous.
"Positions in time, as time appears to us
prima facie, are distinguished in two ways. Each position is Earlier than some,
and Later than some, of the other positions. And each position is either Past,
Present, or Future. The distinctions of the former class are permanent, while
those of the latter are not. If M is ever earlier than N, it is always earlier.
But an event, which is now present, was future and will be past."
McTaggart calls the series of earlier and later the B series, and the Past Present Future series the A series. In the B series, given an event (for McTaggart, the fundamental elements of the two series), its description, with relation to another event, will always be described as earlier or later. C.D. Broad always follows McTaggart down the library-ridden years to the final conflagration. But in the A series, oddly enough, all three descriptions will apply: Broad, let us say, planned to write his book about McTaggart, the book appeared, and the book is now history – which usually means out of print. At one point an event will be in the future, at another point it will be in the present, and at still another point it will be past.
McTaggart throws in another characteristic of time -- he connects it to change. This isn’t a novelty – indeed, Aristotle did the same thing. And it is here that the abstracting of his two series designated under one concept – time – does its work for McTaggart:
McTaggart calls the series of earlier and later the B series, and the Past Present Future series the A series. In the B series, given an event (for McTaggart, the fundamental elements of the two series), its description, with relation to another event, will always be described as earlier or later. C.D. Broad always follows McTaggart down the library-ridden years to the final conflagration. But in the A series, oddly enough, all three descriptions will apply: Broad, let us say, planned to write his book about McTaggart, the book appeared, and the book is now history – which usually means out of print. At one point an event will be in the future, at another point it will be in the present, and at still another point it will be past.
McTaggart throws in another characteristic of time -- he connects it to change. This isn’t a novelty – indeed, Aristotle did the same thing. And it is here that the abstracting of his two series designated under one concept – time – does its work for McTaggart:
“It would,
I suppose, be universally admitted that time involves change. A particular
thing, indeed, may exist unchanged through any amount of time. But when we ask
what we mean by saying that there were different moments of time, or a certain
duration of time, through which the thing was the same, we find that we mean
that it remained the same while other things were changing. A universe in which
nothing whatever changed (including the thoughts of the conscious beings in it)
would be a timeless universe.”
McTaggart
uses a royal example here – which is appropriate for a royal theme, a
Shakespearian theme:
“Take any
event -- the death of Queen Anne, for example -- and consider what change can
take place in its characteristics. That it is a death, that it is the death of
Anne Stuart, that it has such causes, that it has such effects -- every characteristic
of this sort never changes. "Before the stars saw one another plain"
the event in question was a death of an English Queen. At the last moment of
time -- if time has a last moment -- the event in question will still be a
death of an English Queen. And in every respect but one it is equally devoid of
change. But in one respect it does change. It began by being a future event. It
became every moment an event in the nearer future. At last it was present. Then
it became past, and will always remain so, though every moment it becomes
further and further past.”
It is of
interest to note that McTaggart’s series B, of earlier and later, is missing
one crucial English term: “then”. The “then”, of course, introduces into the
immobility of earlier and later the movement from the former to the later. It
introduces something like cause – or, rather, exists as a proxy for cause.
Queen Anne was sick, then she was sicker, then she died. The “then” forecloses
on the abstraction that allows us to separate past present and future from
early and later. The then gives us a sense of time as embedded in possibility:
there is no possible “then” in the sequence from Queen Anne’s sickeness to her
death in which Queen Anne becomes a frog, for instance.
Of course, the “then” also gives a philosophical
hostage to fortune: that is, it requires us to endow cause with an ontological
weight that was dismissed as counterfeit by Berkeley and Hume. “Then” is a
trickster, in as much as cause, if we are right, not only happens within time
but – time happens within cause. Perhaps we have only shifted the paradox in
McTaggart’s essay, really, with our correction. And yet, without the then, we
and our adventures are lost.
It is at this point, as the series – which we also
recognize as Aeon and Chronos, the great Gods of time who are given a thorough working out in
Gilles Deleuze’s Logic of Sense - threaten to
get out of hand, that we can turn to Borges, who of course adored this kind of
play with ideas, and especially the implications of idealism, as it popped the
whole world into a short story that reflects on the order of its own
events - like a watch that stops to ponder whether it will go from
one o’clock to one-o-one, or if, instead, it will go from one clock to the
corner liquor store to buy a bottle of cheap Irish whiskey and sit in the shade
under a tree near a slow street and ponder its doings.
Borges’s essay, A New Refutation of Time, was published in 1947. But, in a sign of the contagion inherent in writing skeptically on time, it was written, according to Borges’ preface, twice, once in 1944, and then again in 1946 – the latter being a revision that Borges then chose to stand alone, splitting the essay into two – and incidentally troping the “New” in his title, making it “new and newer”. Of course, a new refutation of time, if successful, would make it not at all a new refutation of time, as there would be nothing new and nothing old about the enterprise. Such is the nature of the beast, which bucks off every rider – and confutes itself.
Borges doesn’t mention McTaggart. One wonders if
this means he has not read McTaggart – Borges, who read everything. Or
everything odd. Instead, Borges presents his refutation as the logical sum of
the arguments made by Berkeley and Hume against materialism – that is, the
argument that perception proves either something perceived or something
perceiving. And he then – (this then figures in a logical simulacrum of time, a
sort of fixed set of relations, like series A) -- writes:
“Once the idealist argument is admitted, I see that
it is possible -- perhaps inevitable -- to go further. For Berkeley, time is
"the succession of ideas in my mind, which flows uniformly, and is
participated by all beings" (Principles of Human Knowledge, 98); for
Hume, "a succession of indivisible moments" (Treatise of
Human Nature, I, 2, 2). However, once matter and spirit -- which are
continuities -- are negated, once space too is negated, I do not know with what
right we retain that continuity which is time. Outside each perception (real or
conjectural) matter does not exist; outside each mental state spirit does not
exist; neither does time exist outside each present moment.”
To explain this, and to shadow forth its
consequences (the latter is the inveterate essayist’s gesture – the philosopher
would, strictly, value only the first task) Borges uses an unroyal example,
even an exotic one:
“Outside each perception (real or conjectural ) ,
matter does not exist; outside each mental state,
spirit does not exist; neither then must time exist
outside each present moment. Let us choose a moment of the utmost simplicity,
for example, Chuang Tzu's dream ( Herbert Allen Giles, Chuang Tzu, 1899 ). Some
twenty four centuries ago, Chuang Tzu dreamed he was a butterfly, and when he
awoke he was not sure whether he was a man who had dreamed he was a butterfly
or a butterfly who dreamed he was a man. … according to Berkeley, at that
moment the body of Chuang Tzu did not exist, nor did the dark bedroom in
which he was dreaming, save as a perception in the
mind of God. Humesimplifies what happened even more: at that moment the spirit
of ChuangTzu did not exist; all that existed were the colors of the dream and
the certainty of his being a butterfly.
He existed as a momentary term in the "bundle or coilection of different
perceptions" which constituted, some four centuries before Christ, the
mind of Chuang Tzu; he existed as the term n in an infinite temporal series,
between n - 1 and n + 1. There is no other reality for idealism than mental
processes; to add an objective butterfly to the butterfly one perceives
therefore seems a vain duplication; to add a self to the mental processes
seems, therefore, no less exorbitant.”
Vacuuming up time, Borges is saying, means that we
will (accidentally) vacuum up the self. Once time goes, identity follows.
And yet, oddly enough, while identity is cast out
to howl and gnash its teach, particularities rule the world. For, note, in both
McTaggart’s vision and Borges’, everything favors order – the frame in which
events are related - and disfavors one
cause – the great enemy of idealism. It is the hidden love of order that lies
behind the most radical gesture of the British idealist school. It is that
order, really, that Borges loves, even as he cannot, really, believe his own
refutation of time, or its consequences. Borges finds a beautiful literary
allusion to end his meditation.
A Buddhist
treatise of the fifth
century, the Visuddhimagga (Road to Purity),
illustrates the same doctrine… "Strictly speaking, the duration of the
life of a living being is exceedingly brief,
lasting only while a thought lasts. Just as a chariot
wheel in rolling rolls only at one point of the tire, and in resting rests only
at one point; in exactly the same way the life of a living being lasts only for
the period of one thought."
A thought that nobody thinks, about a thing that
exists only in the thought, that endures in a medium that negates all
endurance: can there be a greater escape from adventure? This is the key to the
Borgesian short story, an absolute in its genre just as Mallarme’s “Un coup de
des n’abolira jamais l’hasard” is an absolute of its genre, poetry. It is an
absolute in a genre that arose out of the word limits of the periodical press:
that dispensed with the oral weight of the tale, but with a guilty conscience.
It makes an existential value out of the “shortness” of the story, but one that
is embedded in a disappointed idealism, where the emblematic is trapped, like a
royal death in a timeless world, in an order that refers to itself alone, an order that cannot, logically, be dynastic, but that is pervaded by the pathos of dethroned dynasty.
No comments:
Post a Comment