It is said that Chryssipus the Stoic held that there were,
for all problems, true solutions. But he also held that at times, we can’t see
them – and those times called for a morally disciplined silence. It is in this
spirit he approached the paradox of the heap – the sorites. The paradox is as
follows: if we construct a heap from seeds, say, we can, by adding seeds
successively, reach a point where we might say that we have a heap, and
identify that with the number of seeds we have used – say, 200. And yet, when
we subtract one seed, we are disinclined to say that we no longer have a heap.
Given that fact, we might play the game by claiming that we haven’t reached a
heap no matter how many seeds we use in order to avoid identifying the heap
with a certain number of seeds – but then, paradoxically, we will never achieve
a heap. In fact, we don’t really seem to be able to quantify a thing like a
heap; neither do we want to say that the heap is a quality when clearly it can
be analyzed into its separate parts. To borrow a term from contemporary logic, there is no “heapmaker” – so how can there be
a heap? Chryssipus, according to Sextus Empiricus, recommended that “when
the Sorites is being propounded one should, while the argument is proceeding,
stop and suspend judgement to avoid falling into absurdity.” Analytic philosophers, such as Mario
Magnucci, who wrote a seminal paper on the stoic response to the sorites, have
attempted to incorporate Chryssipus’s response into standard Western logic. To
me, the stoic response is closer to the notion of Mu in Rinzai Zen. The famous
Mu Koan goes like this: a disciple of Zhaozhou, a Chinese zen master, asked him
if a dog has the Buddha nature. Zhaouzhou answered Wu – Mu in Japanese – which
means no, empty, vacant, and – it is said – applies in different ways to the
question: that there is no dog, that there is no Buddha nature, that the dog
does not have Buddha nature, and so on. In other words, the answer is meant to
break the mental habit of thinking that the way of assembly – where distinct
parts are put together – and the way of disassembly, where distinct parts are
separated, are grounded in the real. Indetermination is neither a fact of the
real nor not a fact of the real.
Too often, disputes among historians
about the rise or decline of some historical property fail to acknowledge that
rise and fall are sorites. Hence, arguments become very vicious about what the
risemakers or the fall-makers are, and when they occur. Accepting that
historical narratives have a sorites paradox at their center helps us clarify
the half-fictitious natur e of the business. Even if one doesn’t stop and fall
silent, like Chryssipus, one has to accept the possibility that finally,
withdrawal is the correct response.
Which is an elaborate detour on the way
to approaching the vexed question of the “rise of capitalism” in Western
Europe, which basically means England and France, in the eighteenth
century. Of course,Great Britain and
France were mainly agricultural –as was the US until 1900. But the question is
not just about the rise of industrialism, but the monetarization of agriculture
and the emergence of a market system – and the emergence of a “spirit” of
capitalism.
That spirit has been poked and
probed since, well, the eighteenth century itself. One aspect of it seems to me
to be a little less sore from the prodding: the re-evaluation of competition.
In James Steaurt’s Inquiry into the Principles of Political
Economy (1767), there’s an interesting footnote that briefly outlines a
counterfactual history stemming from the hypothesis that the Fall neveer took
place.
“Hence
I conclude, that had the fall never taken place,the pursuits of man would have
been totally different from
what they are at present. Mayl be
allowed to suppose, that in such a happy state, he might have been endowed with a faculty of
transmitting his most complex ideas with the same perspicuity
with which we now transmit those relating to geometry, numbers, colors,
&c. From this I infer, there would have been no difference of sentiment, no
dispute, no competition between man and man. The progress in acquiring useful knowledge, the pleasure of
communicating discoveries , would alone have provided a fond of happiness, as inexhaustible as knowledge itself.”
The joke in making paradise
into the Isle of Laputa was no longer
funny fifty years after Swift to the moral philosophers of the Scottish school
– nor, in fact, to the whole tribe of
improving theoreticians who Burke attacks in the Reflections.
More on this later.
1 comment:
I love this comment:
So one of the things that articles about machine automation replacing human workers tend to miss is that although machines can replace the physical labor of humans, and can increasingly replace the intellectual labor of humans, no extant machine has a human capacity for suffering, or our unique ability to submit to pain. This is why, as more and more blue-collar and white-collar jobs have been replaced with machine labor, workers haven't stopped working or whatever. Instead, we've been moved into service jobs where our value to employers comes primarily from our ability to perform our own suffering — to scrape and bow for our betters, no matter how stupid their demands are, no matter how much we have to ignore our own needs to service their wants.
Until such time as machines can show real agony, and then (and this is important) mask that real agony behind a waitron's fake smile, we won't starve. Instead we'll continue to be employed supplying affective labor for the people who matter.
http://www.metafilter.com/148962/Automation-is-coming-but-how-will-labor-adapt
Post a Comment