In 1877, John
Tyndall gave an address in Belfast that
was emblematic of the high and confident positivism of the time. In one
passage, he violates one of the canons of Victorian gentility – the Oxford
variety – by aligning himself with the gloriously vulgar tradition, going back
to Francis Bacon, of using Aristotle, conceived of as the father of a lot
of a priori nonsense, as an all purpose punching bag:
“…in Aristotle, as in Goethe, it was not, I believe, misdirection, but sheer
natural incapacity which lay at the root of his mistakes. As a physicist,
Aristotle displayed what we should consider some of the worst attributes of a
modern physical investigator: indistinctness of ideas, confusion of mind, and a
confident use of language, which led to the delusive notion that he had really
mastered his subject, while he had as yet failed to grasp even the elements of
it. He put words in the place of things, subject in the place of object. He
preached Induction without practising it, inverting the true order of inquiry
by passing from the general to the particular, instead of from the particular
to the general. He made of the universe a closed sphere, in the centre of which
he fixed the earth, proving from general principles, to his own satisfaction
and to that of the world for near 2,000 years, that no other universe was
possible. His notions of motion were entirely unphysical. It was natural or
unnatural, better or worse, calm or violentóno real mechanical conception
regarding it lying at the bottom of his mind. He affirmed that a vacuum could
not exist, and proved that if it did exist motion in it would be impossible. He
determined a priori how many species of animals must exist, and shows on
general principles why animals must have such and such parts. When an eminent
contemporary philosopher, who is far removed from errors of this kind,
remembers these abuses of the a priori method, he will be able to make
allowance for the jealousy of physicists as to the acceptance of so-called a
priori truths. Aristotle's errors of detail, as shown by Eucken and Lange, were
grave and numerous. He affirmed that only in man we had the beating of the
heart, that the left side of the body was colder than the right, that men have
more teeth than women, and that there is an empty space at the back of every
man's head.
There is one essential quality in physical conceptions which was entirely
wanting in those of Aristotle and his followers. I wish it could be expressed
by a word untainted by its associations; it signifies a capability of being
placed as a coherent picture before the mind. The Germans express the act of
picturing by the word vorstellen, and the picture they call a Vorstellung. We
have no word in English which comes nearer to our requirements than
Imagination, and, taken with its proper limitations, the word answers very
well; but, as just intimated, it is tainted by its associations, and therefore
objectionable to some minds.”
Tyndall’s groping attempt to put his chemical stained fingers around a term to
distinguish a distinct, yet under-conceptualized mental act – and
can’t one feel him almost painfully balance just on the edge of the unknown
word, like Watson trying to follow one of Holmes’ points – eerily points to the
need that was met ten years later, when just the thing emerged under the pen of
a German physicist, Ernst Mach. The Gedanken-experiment was born.
Ever since, it has been retrospectively accorded to other times and conceptual
schemes. I have always found this a rather uncomfortable anachronism. But what
I’d like to consider is how, exactly, the thought experiment is an experiment.
We don’t kid ourselves that our objections will squelch the word. We don’t want
to. The relation between the thought experiment and the experiment is like the
relation between the red breasted American thrush and the English robin: they
look enough alike that English settlers in the New World called the thrush a
robin. Lexically, only a pedant would object to that – taxonomically, it is a
disaster.
A common defense of thought experiments, among philosophers, is that thought
experiments are a common element of science. In fact, we have read claims
that in certain scientific discourses, they have an essential function. I don’t
doubt it. However, the move from saying that that class of things that we call
“thought experiments” play a role in science to saying that they are indeed a
type of experiment is not dependent on a clear view of experiments, but on the
prestige of science, which is considered to be ultimately experimental. In
other words, we are eye to eye with a vicious circle. Prestige, here,
underwrites this logical leap. What it tells us is two things: we are dealing,
first of all, with myth; and secondly, we are dealing with myth in terms of a
the archaic system of legitimation that consists in referring to authority,
rather than rationality.
Our protest against the prestige of thought experiments in philosophy stems
from our sense of what experiment meant in the first place. Tyndall’s cool
evaluation of Aristotle might not be textually correct re the man himself, but
it is certainly correct about the spirit of Aristotelianism. The introduction
of the experimental method in Europe in the seventeenth century was about one
thing: the art of discovery. The point was to get outside of your head. That
the world outside could be discovered was a tremendously exciting and hazardous
thing.
The mania for thought experiments cruelly inverts this moment. Reflection,
instead of being forced to confront the obdurant outlines of some irrepressible
piece of exteriority, contents itself with the soft and pleasing task of
creating bad fictions in the image of its desires. The movement from Bacon,
whose death as a ‘martyr to experimentation’ is well described by Macaulay to
the spectacle of a Chalmers, doing “consciousness science’ by means of
infantile fantasies of zombies, is a painful indicator that civilization ain’t
what it used to be.
In a conference on thought experiments that was published in the 1992
PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association,
Ian Hacking, one of my favorite philosophers (who has gained this coveted
status by being interested in what is going on outside of his head and studying
it – a rare thing), commented on the papers presented that defended the
validity of the thought experiment. He conceded the force of many of the
arguments for thought experiments, but his emphasis was on the fact that he
felt, in the presence of the thought experiment, unmoved. That is, he felt that
the experiment was not explicative. Experiments, in Hacking’s account, have a
life – thought experiments exist frozen in their pictorial essence. Referring
to Thomas Kuhn’s essay on thought experiments, Hacking points to the character
of good thought experiments:
“… thought experiments are rather fixed, largely immutable. That is yet another
respect that thye are like mathematical proofs, but good proofs have
proof ideas that can be used over and over in new contexts – which is not, in
general the case with thought experiments. They have just one tension to
expose. Of course there are false starts, and the exposition gets neater over
time. And here the prescience of Kuhn’s paper comes to the fore. The reason
that people wrestle with thought experiments, use them for exposition and put-down
argument, is that they can reveal tensions between one vision of the world and
another. They can dislodge a person from a certain way of describing the
worlds. They can replace one picture by another. That is their job, their once
and future job.”
Note: Since I began this number in Victorian prose, let me end it the same way.
Here is Macaulay’s great description of Bacon’s death:
„It had occurred to him that snow might be used with advantage for the purpose
of preventing animal substances from putrefying. On a very cold day, early in the
spring of the year 1626, he alighted from his coach near Highgate, in order to
try the experiment. He went into a cottage, bought a fowl, and with his own
hands stuffed it with snow. While thus engaged he felt a sudden chill, and was
soon so much indisposed that it was impossible for him to return to Gray's Inn.
The Earl of Arundel, with whom he was well acquainted, had a house at Highgate.
To that house Bacon was carried. The Earl was absent; but the servants who were
in charge of the place showed great respect and attention to the illustrious
guest. Here, after an illness of about a week, he expired early on the morning
of Easter-day, 1626. His mind appears to have retained its strength and
liveliness to the end. He did not forget the fowl which had caused his death.
In the last letter that he ever wrote, with fingers which, as he said, could
not steadily hold a pen, he did not omit to mention that the experiment of the
snow had succeeded "excellently well"
“I’m so bored. I hate my life.” - Britney Spears
Das Langweilige ist interessant geworden, weil das Interessante angefangen hat langweilig zu werden. – Thomas Mann
"Never for money/always for love" - The Talking Heads
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
Reviewing, a retrospective
I’ve done my time as a book reviewer. I’ve lived in the foxhole, or the book-reviewer’s equivalent: an efficiency apartment overflowing wi...
-
Being the sort of guy who plunges, headfirst, into the latest fashion, LI pondered two options, this week. We could start an exploratory com...
-
The most dangerous man the world has ever known was not Attila the Hun or Mao Zedong. He was not Adolf Hitler. In fact, the most dangerous m...
-
You can skip this boring part ... LI has not been able to keep up with Chabert in her multi-entry assault on Derrida. As in a proper duel, t...
No comments:
Post a Comment